ֱ̽ of Cambridge - philosophy /taxonomy/subjects/philosophy en Cambridge launches Institute for Technology and Humanity /stories/institute-technology-humanity-launch <div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>A major interdisciplinary initiative has been launched that aims to meet the challenges and opportunities of new technologies as they emerge, today and far into the future.</p> </p></div></div></div> Tue, 21 Nov 2023 09:13:02 +0000 fpjl2 243351 at Making peace /stories/making-peace <div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>Enterprising Mind João Costa has turned a philosophical idea into a practical tool for resolving real-world conflict.</p> </p></div></div></div> Wed, 08 Nov 2023 17:35:53 +0000 skbf2 243151 at New, handwritten Maimonides texts discovered at Cambridge ֱ̽ Library /stories/maimonides-fragments-discovered <div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>900-year-old paper fragment verified as the handwriting of legendary philosopher Maimonides.</p> </p></div></div></div> Thu, 11 May 2023 15:41:27 +0000 sjr81 238961 at Interfering in big decisions friends and family take could violate a crucial moral right, philosopher argues /research/news/interfering-in-big-decisions-friends-and-family-take-could-violate-a-crucial-moral-right-philosopher <div class="field field-name-field-news-image field-type-image field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><img class="cam-scale-with-grid" src="/sites/default/files/styles/content-580x288/public/news/research/news/man-and-woman-speaking-photo-by-charlesdeluvio-on-unsplash-885x428.jpg?itok=mT3-x0-B" alt="Two people speaking, sat at a table" title="Two people speaking, sat at a table, Credit: Charlesdeluvio on Unsplash" /></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-body field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p>If you’ve told an adult friend or family member that they should not take a job, not date someone, not try skydiving or not move abroad, you may have violated a crucial moral right to ‘revelatory autonomy’ and ‘self-authorship’, according to a philosopher at Christ’s College, Cambridge.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Dr Farbod Akhlaghi’s study, published in the journal <em>Analysis</em>, is the first of its kind to suggest that we have a moral right to ‘revelatory autonomy’, that is the right to discover for ourselves who we’ll become as a result of making ‘transformative choices’, choices to have experiences that teach us what that experience will be like for us whilst also changing our core preferences, values and desires.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Dr Akhlaghi says: “ ֱ̽ability to see that the person we’ve become is the product of decisions that we made for ourselves is very important.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>“I’m not telling people what to do. I’m just highlighting part of what is morally at stake in these very common interactions and trying to develop a framework for us to understand them. I hope some may find this helpful, as these will always be difficult moments for all of us.”</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Traditionally, philosophers interested in ‘transformative experiences’ have focused on the decision-maker not on the people who are in a position to influence that person’s choices. But Dr Akhlaghi thinks that these neglected interactions present ‘an urgent ethical challenge’:</p>&#13; &#13; <p>“There are lots of different reasons why we might seek to intervene – some selfish, others well meaning – but whatever our motivation, we can cause significant harm, including to the people we love most.”</p>&#13; &#13; <p>While Akhlaghi accepts that advice can be offered without crossing the moral line, he warns that it is all too easy to slip into various forms of interference, such as forcing, coercing, manipulating or even ‘rationally persuading’ someone away from a transformative choice, in ways that may violate their right to revelatory autonomy.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Akhlaghi says: “Rational persuasion is probably the most common form of interference. Giving, when asked, factual information about a choice that you have knowledge about and the other person does not, can be justified. But while rational persuasion respects someone’s ability to reason, even this form of engagement can involve disrespecting their autonomous self-authorship.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>For example, Akhlaghi continues: “Offering reasons, arguments or evidence as if one is in a privileged position with respect to what the other person’s experience would be like for them disrespects their moral right to revelatory autonomy.”</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Initially inspired to consider this area of moral philosophy by personal experiences, Dr Akhlaghi examines and rejects a number of other conditions under which it could be argued that trying to prevent someone from making transformative choices is morally justified.</p>&#13; &#13; <p><strong>For example</strong></p>&#13; &#13; <p>Dissuading someone from becoming a parent because you think parenthood would make their life worse is problematic because becoming a parent is a positive experience for some and not for others, and no one can know that outcome in advance, even if the person doing the dissuading has experienced being a parent themselves.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>A different example in the study relates to dissuading someone from making a career change that involves a big pay cut because you think that they would struggle to afford their expensive tastes. This is just as problematic, Akhlaghi says, because:</p>&#13; &#13; <p>“We can only know what the future person’s interests are and whether their present interests will be fulfilled after a transformative choice has been made.”</p>&#13; &#13; <p>“ ֱ̽person who changes job might manage to afford their expensive tastes and we don’t even know if that future person would still have these tastes. This highlights another problem – whose interests matter morally when trying to justify interfering: those of the present or the future person?”</p>&#13; &#13; <p><strong>Is it ever right to interfere?</strong></p>&#13; &#13; <p>“It is only permissible to interfere to try to prevent a transformative choice,” Akhlaghi argues “if someone’s right to revelatory autonomy is outweighed by competing moral considerations.”</p>&#13; &#13; <p>A would-be killer’s right to revelatory autonomy is, for instance, plausibly outweighed by the wrongness of killing others solely to discover who they would become by doing so. Equally, protecting a friend from gratuitous self-mutilation would plausibly outweigh their right to autonomously discover what it would be like to harm themselves in this way.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Akhlaghi suggests that the more likely it is that a choice will affect someone’s ‘core preferences, identity and values’, the stronger the moral reasons would need to be to justify interfering in their decision. For instance, interfering in someone’s decision to go to university or not, would require far stronger moral reasons than them choosing whether to eat a cheeseburger or not.</p>&#13; &#13; <p>Finally, Akhlaghi clarifies that his study concerns voluntary choices to have ‘transformative experiences.’ Some such experiences are instead either the unintended consequences of something we did, or ones we are forced into as, for example, children might be by a divorce. These raise different but related problems he hopes to explore in future work.</p>&#13; &#13; <p><strong>Reference</strong></p>&#13; &#13; <p><em>Farbod Akhlaghi, '<a href="https://academic.oup.com/analysis/advance-article/doi/10.1093/analys/anac084/6966040">Transformative experience and the right to revelatory autonomy</a>', Analysis (2022), DOI: 10.1093/analys/anac084</em></p>&#13; </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>We have a moral duty to allow others to make ‘transformative choices’ such as changing careers, migrating and having children, a new study argues. This duty can be outweighed by competing moral considerations such as preventing murder but in many cases we should interfere with far greater caution.</p>&#13; </p></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-quote field-type-text-long field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"> ֱ̽ability to see that the person we’ve become is the product of decisions that we made for ourselves is very important</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-quote-name field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Farbod Akhlaghi</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-credit field-type-link-field field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><a href="/" target="_blank">Charlesdeluvio on Unsplash</a></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-desctiprion field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Two people speaking, sat at a table</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-cc-attribute-text field-type-text-long field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><a href="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/" rel="license"><img alt="Creative Commons License" src="https://i.creativecommons.org/l/by/4.0/88x31.png" style="border-width:0" /></a><br />&#13; ֱ̽text in this work is licensed under a <a href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/">Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License</a>. Images, including our videos, are Copyright © ֱ̽ of Cambridge and licensors/contributors as identified.  All rights reserved. We make our image and video content available in a number of ways – as here, on our <a href="/">main website</a> under its <a href="/about-this-site/terms-and-conditions">Terms and conditions</a>, and on a <a href="/about-this-site/connect-with-us">range of channels including social media</a> that permit your use and sharing of our content under their respective Terms.</p>&#13; </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-show-cc-text field-type-list-boolean field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Yes</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-license-type field-type-taxonomy-term-reference field-label-above"><div class="field-label">Licence type:&nbsp;</div><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><a href="/taxonomy/imagecredit/attribution">Attribution</a></div></div></div> Wed, 25 Jan 2023 07:30:00 +0000 ta385 236421 at Men may not ‘perceive’ domestic tasks as needing doing in the same way as women, philosophers argue /research/news/men-may-not-perceive-domestic-tasks-as-needing-doing-in-the-same-way-as-women-philosophers-argue <div class="field field-name-field-news-image field-type-image field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><img class="cam-scale-with-grid" src="/sites/default/files/styles/content-580x288/public/news/research/news/gender.jpg?itok=a-xACIBO" alt="Wiping down the countertop " title="Wiping down the countertop , Credit: Getty images" /></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-body field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p>Philosophers seeking to answer questions around inequality in household labour and the invisibility of women’s work in the home have proposed a new theory – that men and women are trained by society to see different possibilities for action in the same domestic environment. </p> <p>They say a view called “affordance theory” – that we experience objects and situations as having actions implicitly attached – underwrites the age-old gender disparity when it comes to the myriad mundane tasks of daily home maintenance.</p> <p>For example, women may look at a surface and see an implied action – ‘to be wiped’ – whereas men may just observe a crumb-covered countertop.    </p> <p> ֱ̽philosophers believe these deep-seated gender divides in domestic perception can be altered through societal interventions such as extended paternal leave, which will encourage men to build up mental associations for household tasks.</p> <p>Writing in the journal <em><a href="https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111/phpr.12929">Philosophy and Phenomenological Research</a></em>, they argue that available data – particularly data gathered during the pandemic – suggest two questions require explanation. </p> <p>One is “disparity”: despite economic and cultural gains, why do women continue to shoulder the vast majority of housework and childcare? ֱ̽other is “invisibility”: why do so many men believe domestic work to be more equally distributed than in fact it is?</p> <p>“Many point to the performance of traditional gender roles, along with various economic factors such as women taking flexible work for childcare reasons,” said Dr Tom McClelland, from Cambridge ֱ̽’s Department of History and Philosophy of Science.</p> <p>“Yet the fact that stark inequalities in domestic tasks persisted during the pandemic, when most couples were trapped inside, and that many men continued to be oblivious of this imbalance, means this is not the full story.”</p> <p>McClelland and co-author Prof Paulina Sliwa argue that unequal divisions of labour in the home – and the inability of men to identify said labour – is best explained through the psychological notion of “affordances”: the idea that we perceive things as inviting or “affording” particular actions.</p> <p>“This is not just looking at the shape and size of a tree and then surmising you can climb it, but actually seeing a particular tree as climbable, or seeing a cup as drink-from-able,” said Sliwa, recently of Cambridge’s philosophy faculty and now at the ֱ̽ of Vienna. </p> <p>“Neuroscience has shown that perceiving an affordance can trigger neural processes preparing you for physical action. This can range from a slight urge to overwhelming compulsion, but it often takes mental effort not to act on an affordance.”</p> <p>There are dramatic differences in “affordance perception” between individuals. One person sees a tree as climbable where another does not. Objects offer a vast array of affordances – one could see a spatula as an egg-frying tool or a rhythmic instrument – and a spectrum of sensitivity towards them. </p> <p>“If we apply affordance perception to the domestic environment and assume it is gendered, it goes a long way to answering both questions of disparity and invisibility,” said McClelland.</p> <p>According to the philosophers, when a woman enters a kitchen she is more likely to perceive the “affordances” for particular domestic tasks – she sees the dishes as ‘to be washed’ or a fridge as ‘to be stocked’.</p> <p>A man may simply observe dishes in a sink, or a half-empty fridge, but without perceiving the affordance or experiencing the corresponding mental “tug”. Over time, these little differences add up to significant disparities in who does what.  </p> <p>“Affordances pull on your attention,” said Sliwa. “Tasks may irritate the perceiver until done, or distract them from other plans. If resisted, it can create a felt tension.”</p> <p>“This puts women in a catch-22 situation: either inequality of labour or inequality of cognitive load.”</p> <p>This gender-based split in affordance perception could have a number of root causes, say philosophers. Social cues encourage actions in certain environments, often given by adults when we are very young children. Our visual systems update based on what we encounter most frequently.</p> <p>“Social norms shape the affordances we perceive, so it would be surprising if gender norms do not do the same,” said McClelland.</p> <p>“Some skills are explicitly gendered, such cleaning or grooming, and girls are expected to do more domestic chores than boys. This trains their ways of seeing the domestic environment, to see a counter as ‘to be wiped’.”</p> <p> ֱ̽“gendered affordance perception hypothesis” is not about absolving men say Sliwa and McClelland. Despite a deficit in affordance perception in the home, a man can easily notice what needs doing by thinking rather than seeing. Nor should sensitivity to domestic affordances in women be equated with natural affinity for housework.</p> <p>“We can change how we perceive the world through continued conscious effort and habit cultivation,” said McClelland. “Men should be encouraged to resist gendered norms by improving their sensitivity to domestic task affordances." </p> <p>“A man might adopt a resolution to sweep for crumbs every time he waits for the kettle to boil, for example. Not only would this help them to do the tasks they don't see, it would gradually retrain their perception so they start to see the affordance in the future.”</p> <p>Collective efforts to change social norms require policy-level interventions, argue the philosophers. For example, shared parental leave gives fathers the opportunity to become more sensitive to caring-task affordances.</p> <p>Added Sliwa: “Our focus has been on physical actions such as sweeping or wiping, but gendered affordance perceptions could also apply to mental actions such as scheduling and remembering.”</p> </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>By adding a gender dimension to the theory of “affordance perception” and applying it to the home, a new hypothesis may help answer questions of why women still shoulder most housework, and why men never seem to notice.</p> </p></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-quote field-type-text-long field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Men should be encouraged to resist gendered norms by improving their sensitivity to domestic task affordances</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-content-quote-name field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Tom McClelland</div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-credit field-type-link-field field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><a href="/" target="_blank">Getty images</a></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-desctiprion field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Wiping down the countertop </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-cc-attribute-text field-type-text-long field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><a href="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/" rel="license"><img alt="Creative Commons License" src="https://i.creativecommons.org/l/by/4.0/88x31.png" style="border-width:0" /></a><br /> ֱ̽text in this work is licensed under a <a href="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/">Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License</a>. Images, including our videos, are Copyright © ֱ̽ of Cambridge and licensors/contributors as identified.  All rights reserved. We make our image and video content available in a number of ways – as here, on our <a href="/">main website</a> under its <a href="/about-this-site/terms-and-conditions">Terms and conditions</a>, and on a <a href="/about-this-site/connect-with-us">range of channels including social media</a> that permit your use and sharing of our content under their respective Terms.</p> </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-show-cc-text field-type-list-boolean field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Yes</div></div></div> Thu, 22 Dec 2022 09:39:23 +0000 fpjl2 236101 at ֱ̽philosopher who wants us to think deeply about ordinary things /this-cambridge-life/the-philosopher-who-wants-us-to-think-deeply-about-ordinary-things <div class="field field-name-field-content-summary field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><p><p>Nikhil Krishnan, winner of a 2021 Pilkington Prize for outstanding teaching, says that what he loves about teaching is what he loves about philosophy: you can’t know in advance where it’s going to lead. Outside of the lecture hall he’s unravelling how philosophy came to be what it is today.</p> </p></div></div></div> Wed, 15 Dec 2021 12:56:46 +0000 cg605 228731 at Mind Over Chatter: What is the future? /research/about-research/podcasts/mind-over-chatter-what-is-the-future <div class="field field-name-field-content-image field-type-image field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><img class="cam-scale-with-grid" src="/sites/default/files/styles/content-885x432/public/research/logo-for-uni-website.jpeg?itok=Btfgt0hz" width="885" height="432" alt="Mind Over Chatter podcast logo" /></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-body field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><h2>Season 2, episode 1</h2> <p>This second series of Mind Over Chatter is all about the future - and in this first episode we’re going to be considering what the future even is… Have you ever wondered how time works? It turns out, the answer is a lot more complicated than we thought.</p> <p>Join our wondering and wonderful conversation with philosopher of science Dr Matt Farr, whose work focuses particularly on what it means for time to have a direction, professor of psychology Nicky Clayton, who looks at the evolution and development of intelligence in non-verbal animals and pre-verbal children, and professor of linguistics and philosophy, Kasia Jaszczolt whose research interests combine semantics, pragmatics, and the metaphysics of time </p> <p>We’ll be talking about everything from physics to linguistics… and from broken eggs to Einstein’s theory of relativity. </p> <p><a class="cam-primary-cta" href="https://mind-over-chatter.captivate.fm/listen">Subscribe to Mind Over Chatter</a></p> <div style="width: 100%; height: 170px; margin-bottom: 20px; border-radius: 10px; overflow:hidden;"><iframe frameborder="no" scrolling="no" seamless="" src="https://player.captivate.fm/episode/4df81c2a-158e-4fd0-bbdc-42978d698fdc" style="width: 100%; height: 170px;" title="What is the future?"></iframe></div> <h2>Key points</h2> <p>[04:28] - Does time actually go from past to present to future? And does time really ‘flow’?</p> <p>[09:53] - How do B-theorists deal with entropy? Can you un-break an egg?</p> <p>[14:12] - Recap of the first portion of the episode, reviewing A-theory, B-theory and C-theory of time</p> <p>[18:58] - How the mind understands the subjective concept of time</p> <p>[27:11] - ֱ̽Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis and how the way you talk about language affects the way you perceive and think about things</p> <p>[30:21] - Recap of the second portion of the episode </p> <p>[34:02] - How do the mental and linguistic concepts around time fit with philosophical concepts and physics of time?</p> <p>[45:46] - Is there a conflict between the psychological and linguistic models of time and the way physics handles time?</p> <p>[48:20] - Recap of the last portion of the episode</p> </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-desctiprion field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Mind Over Chatter: ֱ̽Cambridge ֱ̽ Podcast</div></div></div> Thu, 27 May 2021 13:22:48 +0000 ns480 224421 at Mind Over Chatter: What is the future of artificial intelligence? /research/about-research/podcasts/mind-over-chatter-what-is-the-future-of-artificial-intelligence <div class="field field-name-field-content-image field-type-image field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><img class="cam-scale-with-grid" src="/sites/default/files/styles/content-885x432/public/research/logo-for-uni-website_0.jpeg?itok=O1xsQXd6" width="885" height="432" alt="Mind Over Chatter podcast logo" /></div></div></div><div class="field field-name-body field-type-text-with-summary field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even"><h2>Season 2, episode 5</h2> <p>Artificial Intelligence can be found in every aspect of our lives. From A-level grade predicting algorithms to Netflix recommendations, AI is set to change the choices we make and how our personal information will be used. </p> <p><a class="cam-primary-cta" href="https://mind-over-chatter.captivate.fm/listen">Subscribe to Mind Over Chatter</a></p> <p> </p> <div style="width: 100%; height: 170px; margin-bottom: 20px; border-radius: 10px; overflow:hidden;"><iframe frameborder="no" scrolling="no" seamless="" src="https://player.captivate.fm/episode/dc2070a7-acce-4022-a211-3e2626bb0bae" style="width: 100%; height: 170px;" title="What is the future of artificial intelligence?"></iframe></div> <p>In this episode of Mind Over Chatter, we explore the future of AI - its potential benefits and harms. We cover topics ranging from how to make AI ‘ethical’, how the media representation of AI can colour the public’s perception of what the real issues are, and the importance of an international AI regulatory system. </p> <p>Dr Beth Singler, whose research explores the social, ethical, philosophical and religious implications of advances in Artificial Intelligence and robotics, told us about the different cultural consequences of AI, and how the way we think about the future of AI reflects more about society today than the future itself.  </p> <p>Dr John Zerilli, author of ‘A citizen’s guide to artificial intelligence’ shared his views on the consequences of AI for democratic decision-making. </p> <p>Finally, Futurist-in-Residence at the Entrepreneurship Centre at the Judge School, Richard Watson, urged us to conceive of the future of AI in terms of ‘scenario planning’, rather than predicting the future directly. </p> <h2>Key points: </h2> <p>[10:09]- how we think about the future as reflecting on what we think about the present</p> <p>[13:38]- Time for the first recap! </p> <p>[17:55]- the relationship between AI and religion, and the cultural impact of AI</p> <p>[20:35]- being ‘blessed’ and ‘cursed’ by the algorithm</p> <p>[22:04]- democracy and AI. How are we to expect citizens to be informed enough to exercise their voting rights in the best way?</p> <p>[32:27]- Time for recap number two! </p> <p>[45:01]- loss of free agency… or did we never have any?</p> <p>[58:05]- Thinking about the benefit of AI can teach us about what makes a good life</p> </div></div></div><div class="field field-name-field-image-desctiprion field-type-text field-label-hidden"><div class="field-items"><div class="field-item even">Mind Over Chatter: ֱ̽Cambridge ֱ̽ Podcast</div></div></div> Thu, 27 May 2021 12:49:38 +0000 ns480 224381 at